Standard argument against free will: Difference between revisions
imported>John R. Brews m (→Doyle) |
imported>John R. Brews m (→Doyle) |
||
Line 103: | Line 103: | ||
:"Physical determinism is not 'true' because physics is empirical, not logical. And the empirical evidence has never justified the assumption of strict determinism." | :"Physical determinism is not 'true' because physics is empirical, not logical. And the empirical evidence has never justified the assumption of strict determinism." | ||
This argument is one of those made by Fischer as well, | This argument is one of those made by Fischer as well, among those discussed next. | ||
===Fischer=== | ===Fischer=== |
Revision as of 13:25, 21 November 2013
The standard argument against free will is an argument that there exists a conflict between the possibility of free will and the postulates of determinism and indeterminism. A formal statement of the 'standard argument' can be phrased as follows:[1][2]
- 1. The concept of determinism contradicts that of free will.
- 2. The concept of indeterminism also contradicts free will.
- 3. Some occurrences are governed by determinism, and all the rest by indeterminism.
all of which lead to the conclusion:
- 4. Free will does not govern any occurrences (does not exist).
The first two premises sometimes are referred to as the "deterministic" and "indeterministic" horns of the dilemma of determinism.[3] The third premise is sometimes stated as: "Either causal determinism is true, or it is false",[2] which is ambiguous regarding whether 'true' and 'false' are used in a logical sense, identifying mutually exclusive and exhaustive definitions, or are used to describe some empirical claim about how things happen.
The formulation of the 'standard argument' above is abstract, avoiding particular definitions of 'determinism' and 'indeterminism' and 'free will' as matters best left out of the formulation itself. These definitions can then be subjected to further detailed discussion comparing the many views about what these terms mean.
The standard argument also commonly is phrased in terms of moral responsibility, rather than free will, as is discussed next.
Moral responsibility
The idea of free will is closely connected to that of moral responsibility, inasmuch as there are reservations over holding an agent responsible for actions where they lacked free will to choose or, perhaps, lacked the capacity to exercise their decisions. Because our intuition of moral responsibility is strong and is, in fact, embedded in many countries' laws meting out punishment for crimes, the issue of moral responsibility is at the same time more personally challenging and more practically important than the 'standard argument', which may appear to be a largely academic dispute over the domains of applicability of determinism and indeterminism, or over terminology and usage.
Versions of the 'standard argument'
At this point, several different formulations of the 'standard argument' are presented. They all fit into the formulation of the introduction by adopting various definitions for the terms 'determinism' and 'indeterminism' and 'free will'.
Doyle
Doyle poses the argument as follows:[1]
- 1. If our actions are determined, the will is not free.
- 2. If indeterminism and real chance exist, our will would not be under our control.
- 3. We could not be responsible for our actions if they are determined, or if they are random.
Doyle calls the first statement the 'determinism objection' and the second the 'randomness objection'. These two statements combine empirical and logical elements, and so complicate their discussion. Doyle does not include explicitly in the standard argument the premise that the choices of determinism and chance exhaust the possibilities. He continues (p. 17): "the "logical" standard argument against free will has been used by some philosophers ...to deny the existence of moral responsibility."
Fischer
Fischer frames the matter so 'free will', 'determinism' and 'indeterminism' in the introduction are replaced by a particular wording, and 'free will' is tied to a particular formulation of 'moral responsibility'. Fischer provides two versions. The first he attributes to William James, although it is Fischer's distillation of James' views,[4] and is not stated this way by James himself:
- 1. Casual determinism means I have to act as I do, and thus am not morally responsible for my actions.
- 2. The only meaningful alternative to causal determinism is that how I act is a matter of luck, and thus I am not morally responsible for my actions.
and one claim, possibly of putative fact, or possibly merely a tautological proposition:
- 3. Either casual determinism is true, or it is false.
which statements in combination lead to the conclusion, which again may be a claim of fact, or a claim of logical consequence:
- 4. Therefore, I am not morally responsible for my actions.
His second formulation is as follows:
- 1. Casual determinism means I cannot do otherwise, and thus am not morally responsible for my actions.
- 2. If causal determinism is false (in a relevant way, that is, in the sequences leading to my behavior) then my actions are not appropriately connected to my prior states (that is, "my actions" are not in a genuine sense my actions) and thus I am not morally responsible for my actions.
and one claim, possibly of putative fact, or possibly merely a tautological proposition:
- 3. Either casual determinism is true, or it is false.
which statements in combination lead to the conclusion, which again may be a claim of fact, or a claim of logical consequence:
- 4. Therefore, I am not morally responsible for my actions.
Comparison shows that Fischer is concerned with distinctions between various formulations of what 'determinism' is and whether free will is to be contrasted with compulsion or with causation (an issue raised by Hume, see below). In sum, the issues raised hinge very much upon definitions and usage, and not so much upon empirical validation (factual evidence).
If we look at Fisher's formulations, they (i) employ a particular definition of determinism, (ii) define indeterminism in different ways in the second premise (iii) introduce a particular view of responsibility and (iv) are ambiguous whether the words 'true' and 'false' are meant throughout in a logical sense (a matter of consistency in usage) as in the first two statements, or changes meaning to an empirical sense in the third claim and in the conclusion (which is a matter of applying assertions to the universe). A decision between these two interpretations decides whether the entire formulation is a purely theoretical logical construction without implication for the real world, or is intended as an empirical claim about the real world. Further examination (see below) of Fischer's text will clarify that Fischer views the argument as having empirical consequences.
Objections to the 'standard argument'
The counter-intuitive conclusion of the 'standard argument', the conclusion that free will does not exist, is inescapable if one accepts the premises of the argument. So attempts to restore confidence in our intuition (and laws) based upon free will take two forms: (i) defining the terms 'determinism', 'indeterminism' and 'free will' in various ways that make the conclusion less clearly in opposition to intuition, and (ii) denying the third premise that it is an empirical fact that an 'either/or' formulation actually applies to the universe as we know it. Writers like Fischer[2] take the first path, and others like Hume,[5] Kant,[6] and James[4] take the second.
Hume
In 1739, David Hume in his A Treatise of Human Nature directed his attention to the conflict between determinism and moral responsibility (free will). Russell discusses Hume's approach using the figure below:[5]
- (A) Chance (B) Humean necessity (C) Metaphysical necessity
- No regular succession Regular succession "Compelling" powers in objects
- ↑ ↑ ↑
- Moral realm?
- Humean necessity and the dilemma of determinism
According to Russell:[5] "Hume is arguing that a middle path may be traveled between, on the one hand, a confused and unintelligible conception of necessity and, on the other, an erroneous belief in the existence of chance." Russell describes Hume's approach in terms of a dilemma, although Hume did not use that terminology:[5] "In the light of the above diagram, it appears evident that Hume's strategy is to reveal that the dilemma of determinism, presented as an alternative between horns A and C, is a false dilemma. The standard dilemma of determinism is taken to be the choice between A and C and, according to Hume, it is a false dilemma because there is the third choice B."[5] The notion is that one must examine more closely the relation between necessity and cause.
Kant
An influential approach to denying the empirical premise of the 'standard argument' was taken in the 1780's by Immanuel Kant, who had high confidence in the authority of intuition, and suggested that moral matters were to be analyzed as lying outside the rules governing material objects.[6] "There is a sharp difference between moral judgments and judgments of fact...Moral judgments ... must be a priori judgments."[7] Evidently, the 'standard argument' does not apply under these conditions, as our moral decision processes lie outside the reach of everyday causality.
According to Suppes:[8]
- "Unfortunately, not many philosophers..would be prepared today to follow Kant's way out of the dilemma of determinism."
However, contradicting that view, according to Velasquez:[9]
- "Many writers today agree with Kant. The philosopher/psychologist Steven Pinker, for example writes the following:
- 'Science and morality are separate spheres of reasoning...[more of this quote is provided]'[10]
- Here Pinker is agreeing with Kant. ... So are we free or determined? Are we responsible agents or passive victims? Was Darrow right? Or was Sartre right? Or were both right as Kant and Pinker suggest?"
James
In 1884 William James presented a talk entitled The Dilemma of Determinism in which he attacked the notion of determinism as simply a convention of the mind used to organize our inchoate sense impressions:[4]
- "I myself believe that all the magnificent achievements of mathematical and physical science — our doctrines of evolution, of uniformity of law, and the rest — proceed from our indomitable desire to cast the world into a more rational shape in our minds than the shape into which it is thrown there by the crude order of our experience. The world has shown itself, to a great extent, plastic to this demand of ours for rationality. How much further it will show itself plastic no one can say...If a certain formula for expressing the nature of the world violates my moral demand, I shall feel as free to to throw it overboard, or at least to doubt it, as if it disappointed my demand of uniformity of sequence...The principle of causality, for example, — what is it but a postulate, an empty name covering a demand that the sequence of events...manifest a deeper kind of belonging of one thing with another than the mere arbitrary juxtaposition which now phenomenally appears?"
Having, he thought, demolished the notion of determinism as a mere device of the mind, James then proposed that chance was the more realistic alternative:
- "And this at last brings us within sight of our subject. We have seen what determinism means: we have seen that indeterminism is rightly described as meaning chance; and we have seen that chance, the very name of which we agreed to shrink from...means only the negative fact that no part of the world, however big, can claim to control absolutely the destinies of the whole"
James' definition of chance is very much broader than that of many modern writers, who view chance as just a roll of the dice. In particular, James' view is compatible with Kant's, although not the same.
Doyle
Doyle's formulation of the 'standard argument' is presented above. He has detailed a number of objections.[1] One of these is the following:
- "Physical determinism is not 'true' because physics is empirical, not logical. And the empirical evidence has never justified the assumption of strict determinism."
This argument is one of those made by Fischer as well, among those discussed next.
Fischer
Fischer's formulation of the 'standard argument' is presented above. He proceeds as follows:[2]
- "I shall argue that neither the [first] premises of the parallel arguments nor the [second] premises are true, and thus the argument is unsound for two separate reasons. I shall further argue that similar considerations help to establish the failure of both the deterministic and indeterministic horns of the dilemma." [Numbering has been changed to match the presentation of this article.]
He then argues that the view that causal determinism implies that we never have the freedom to do other than we actually do, for example, the 'consequence argument' of Van Inwagen,[11] fails because it exaggerates beyond any possibility of real-world attempt at verification, and presupposes a form for scientific laws beyond any supportable claim inasmuch as these laws are limited in scope and their precise form is restricted to what we know of them today.[12]
- "If we knew that determinism were true and we also knew both the natural laws and the complete description of the universe at the present (or at any point in the past), we could predict with certainty whether or not the house will be destroyed by an earthquake. But in fact we do not know the natural laws or whether they are deterministic; and we do not have available such a description."
Actually, this argument critiques not the definitions of various terms (impacting premises 1 and 2 of the introduction), but the empirical premise of the standard argument (item 3 in the introduction) and is close to what Hume, Kant and James also claim.
However, Fischer views this criticism to be controversial, and proposes instead "to attack the contention that moral responsibility requires freedom to choose and do otherwise". Fischer "contend[s] that it is not the case that all causally deterministic sequences crowd out moral responsibility". "We have found plausible and 'independent' arguments for the resilience of moral responsibility to the truth or falsity of causal determinism--arguments that are not simply statements of the desirability of such resilience. In the end, then, moral responsibility is neither inconceivable nor puzzling."[2]
References
- ↑ 1.0 1.1 1.2 Bob Doyle (2011). “The standard argument against free will”, Free Will: The Scandal in Philosophy. I-Phi Press, p. 27. ISBN 098358026X.
- ↑ 2.0 2.1 2.2 2.3 2.4 John Martin Fischer (2011). “§4.1 The dilemma of determinism”, Michael Freeman, ed: Law and Neuroscience: Current Legal Issues. Oxford University Press, pp. 41 ff. ISBN 019959984X. On-line version found here.
- ↑ In his presentation The dilemma of determinism Fischer uses these terms not in reference to 'free will', but to the closely related issue of moral responsibility for our actions. The 'horns' of the dilemma also occur in Russell's discussion of Hume. Doyle's version of the standard argument refers to the 'determinism objection' and the 'randomness objection' to free will.
- ↑ 4.0 4.1 4.2 An address to Harvard Divinity School students in Divinity Hall on March 13, 1884: William James (1886). “The dilemma of determinism”, The Will to Believe: And Other Essays in Popular Philosophy, Reprint. Longmans, Green, and Company, pp. 145 ff. On-line text here
- ↑ 5.0 5.1 5.2 5.3 5.4 Paul Russell (1995). Freedom and Moral Sentiment : Hume's Way of Naturalizing Responsibility. Oxford University Press, p. 51. ISBN 0198025548.
- ↑ 6.0 6.1 R Kevin Hill (2003). “Chapter 7: The critique of morality: The three pillars of Kantian ethics”, Nietzsche's Critiques : The Kantian Foundations of His Thought, Paperback, pp. 196-201. ISBN 0199285527.
- ↑ Herbert James Paton (1971). “§2 Moral judgements are a priori”, The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant's Moral Philosophy. University of Pennsylvania Press, p. 20. ISBN 0812210239.
- ↑ See the discussion of Kant's views in Patrick Suppes (1993). “§4 Irrelevance of physical determinism”, Models and Methods in the Philosophy of Science: Selected Essays. Springer, pp. 479-480. ISBN 0792322118.
- ↑ Manuel Velasquez (2012). “§3.7: Is freedom real?”, Philosophy, 12th. Cengage Learning, p. 211. ISBN 1133612105.
- ↑ Steven Pinker (2009). “Standard equipment”, How the mind works. WW Norton & Co, p. 55. ISBN 0393069737.
- ↑ Peter van Inwangen (1986). “The problems and how we shall approach them”, An Essay on Free Will. Oxford University Press, p. 16. ISBN 0198249241. “Consequence Argument: If determinism is true, then our acts are the consequences of the laws of mature and events in the past. But it is not up to us what went on before we were born, and neither is it up to us what the laws of nature are. Therefore the consequences of these things (including our present acts) are not up to us.”
- ↑ JM Fischer (July 2005). "Dennett on the basic argument". Metaphilosophy 36: p. 434.