Welfare economics: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Nick Gardner
No edit summary
imported>Nick Gardner
(Second redraft)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{subpages}}
{{subpages}}
The concept of welfare is concerned with the  well-being of the individual, and the subject matter of welfare economics is the influence of collective decisions upon the  welfare of groups of individuals. The theorems of welfare economics provide the theoretical basis for the benefits of market [[competition]], the determinants of [[economic efficiency]], the practice of [[cost-benefit analysis]] and many other aspects of economic theory.
The concept of welfare is concerned with the  well-being of the individual, and the subject matter of welfare economics is the influence of collective decisions upon the  welfare of groups of individuals. The theorems of welfare economics provide the theoretical basis for the benefits of market [[competition]], the determinants of [[economic efficiency]], the practice of [[cost-benefit analysis]] and many other aspects of economic theory.
The terms shown in ''italics'' in this article are defined on related article the subpage.


==Definition==
==Definition==
The definition of the welfare of an individual is the same as the definition of [[utility]] that is presented in the article on that subject, but the problem of defining collective or "social" welfare is greatly complicated by the logical impossibility, noted in that article, of making inter-personal comparisons of utility. The nature of that problem is discussed on the tutorials subpage, where it is noted that no completely satisfactory theoretical solution is available. Applied  welfare economics consequently provides only  partial ad-hoc solutions,  qualified by the need to embody value judgments without totally abandoning the presumption that every individual is the sole judge of his own welfare. In many cases, however, the judgments required are so widely accepted as to present no practical  difficulty. There is general acceptance, for example, that  gains in individual welfare arising from psychotic satisfactions are not admissible components of social welfare.
The definition of the welfare of an individual is the same as the definition of [[utility]] that is presented in the article on that subject, but the problem of defining collective or "social" welfare is greatly complicated by the logical impossibility, noted in that article, of making inter-personal comparisons of utility. The nature of that problem is discussed on the tutorials subpage, where it is noted that no completely satisfactory theoretical solution is available. Applied  welfare economics consequently provides only  partial ad-hoc solutions,  qualified by the need to embody value judgments without totally abandoning the presumption that every individual is the sole judge of his own welfare. In many cases, however, the judgments required are so widely accepted as to present no practical  difficulty. There is general acceptance, for example, that  gains in individual welfare arising from psychotic satisfactions are not admissible components of social welfare.


==Competition and welfare==
==The fundamental theorems==
The fundamental theorems of welfare economics define properties of an intensely hypothetical economy in which there are markets that supply  every demand, each of which operates in conditions of ''perfect competition'' and  ''flexible prices'',  and  which together are in ''general equilibrium''.


===Efficiency: the Pareto criterion===
In such an economy there are no ''externalities'', no ''spillovers'', and no ''public goods''; every firm operates on its ''production possibility frontier'', the price of every product is equal to its ''marginal cost'' of production, and every  wage rate is equal to its wage-earner's ''marginal product''.
The aggregate increase in welfare resulting from an action cannot be quantified because interpersonal comparisons of welfare are conceptually impossible. However, it is possible to determine whether an activity increases or  decreases an individual's economic welfare. One way of overcoming the conceptual barrier is to deem that an activity will increase efficiency only if it makes somebody better off without making anybody worse off. Efficiency so defined is termed ''Pareto efficiency'' in honour of the economist, Vilfredo Pareto, who first put that definition forward. The term ''Pareto efficient''  is used to describe an ideal state of affairs from which it is impossible to make a change which would make anybody better off without making somebody else worse off. The Pareto criterion is  often modified for general use by the introduction of the  ''compensation principle'', according to which  efficiency is increased if those who gain as the result of an action could benefit from it after compensating those who lose from it.


===Competition and efficiency===
*The first theorem states that every complete  economy that is entirely made up of  perfectly competitive markets is ''Pareto-efficient'' when in general equilibrium. 
The propositions that are termed the ''fundamental theorems of welfare economics'' define the properties of a market that is in equilibrium and has the hypothetical characteristic of ''perfect competition'' <ref> The requirements for perfect competition are stated in the article on [[competition]]</ref>.
*The second theorem states that other characteristics of such an economy  can be changed without limit without departing from  its Pareto-efficient condition, provided that all of its markets continue to be perfectly competitive.  


====The first fundamental theorem of welfare economics====
One  implication  of the second theorem is that it is theoretically possible for a government to alter the distribution of wealth without causing the economy to depart from an initially Pareto-efficient condition, provided that it does so without creating departures from perfect competition and flexible pricing. The proviso excludes the use of instruments that alter consumer choice (such as sales taxes, that distort choices between products, and income tax, which distorts the choice between consumption and leisure) leaving only unconditional lump-sum taxes such as a poll tax or a tax on land values.  
The first theorem states that every complete  economy that is entirely made up of perfectly competitive markets is  Pareto-efficient when in equilibrium. In the hypothetical economy of the theorem there must be a market to satisfy every human want, with no externalities <ref> The term externality is explained in the article on [[microeconomics]]</re> and no [[public good]]s.


====The second fundamental theorem of welfare economics====
The practical significance of the fundamental theorem is  limited by the the theorem of the second best, which states that an increase in the competitiveness of one  market in an economy in which some other market is not perfectly competitive, does not necessarily increase efficiency.
The second theorem states that the characteristics of an economy that is made up of perfectly competitive markets can be changed without limit while retaining its Pareto-efficiency, provided that all of its markets continue to be perfectly competitive. One  implication  of this theorem is that it is theoretically possible for a government to alter the distribution of wealth without causing the economy to depart from an initially Pareto-efficient condition, provided that it does so without creating departures from perfect competition. The proviso excludes the use of instruments that alter choices (such as sales taxes, that distort choices between products, and income tax, which distorts the choice between consumption and leisure) leaving only unconditional lump-sum taxes such as a poll tax or a tax on land values.  


====The theorem of the second-best====
==Applied welfare economics==
The practical significance of the fundamental theorems is further limited by the the theorem of the second best, which states that an increase in the competitiveness of one  market in an economy in which some other market is not  perfectly competitive, does not necessarily increase efficiency.


==The components of efficiency==
===The components of efficiency===


==Cost-benefit analysis==
===Cost-benefit analysis===


==Other applications==
===Other applications===


==References==
==References==
<references/>
<references/>

Revision as of 02:57, 13 April 2008

This article is developing and not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
Tutorials [?]
 
This editable Main Article is under development and subject to a disclaimer.

The concept of welfare is concerned with the well-being of the individual, and the subject matter of welfare economics is the influence of collective decisions upon the welfare of groups of individuals. The theorems of welfare economics provide the theoretical basis for the benefits of market competition, the determinants of economic efficiency, the practice of cost-benefit analysis and many other aspects of economic theory.

The terms shown in italics in this article are defined on related article the subpage.

Definition

The definition of the welfare of an individual is the same as the definition of utility that is presented in the article on that subject, but the problem of defining collective or "social" welfare is greatly complicated by the logical impossibility, noted in that article, of making inter-personal comparisons of utility. The nature of that problem is discussed on the tutorials subpage, where it is noted that no completely satisfactory theoretical solution is available. Applied welfare economics consequently provides only partial ad-hoc solutions, qualified by the need to embody value judgments without totally abandoning the presumption that every individual is the sole judge of his own welfare. In many cases, however, the judgments required are so widely accepted as to present no practical difficulty. There is general acceptance, for example, that gains in individual welfare arising from psychotic satisfactions are not admissible components of social welfare.

The fundamental theorems

The fundamental theorems of welfare economics define properties of an intensely hypothetical economy in which there are markets that supply every demand, each of which operates in conditions of perfect competition and flexible prices, and which together are in general equilibrium.

In such an economy there are no externalities, no spillovers, and no public goods; every firm operates on its production possibility frontier, the price of every product is equal to its marginal cost of production, and every wage rate is equal to its wage-earner's marginal product.

  • The first theorem states that every complete economy that is entirely made up of perfectly competitive markets is Pareto-efficient when in general equilibrium.
  • The second theorem states that other characteristics of such an economy can be changed without limit without departing from its Pareto-efficient condition, provided that all of its markets continue to be perfectly competitive.

One implication of the second theorem is that it is theoretically possible for a government to alter the distribution of wealth without causing the economy to depart from an initially Pareto-efficient condition, provided that it does so without creating departures from perfect competition and flexible pricing. The proviso excludes the use of instruments that alter consumer choice (such as sales taxes, that distort choices between products, and income tax, which distorts the choice between consumption and leisure) leaving only unconditional lump-sum taxes such as a poll tax or a tax on land values.

The practical significance of the fundamental theorem is limited by the the theorem of the second best, which states that an increase in the competitiveness of one market in an economy in which some other market is not perfectly competitive, does not necessarily increase efficiency.

Applied welfare economics

The components of efficiency

Cost-benefit analysis

Other applications

References