Formal fuzzy logic: Difference between revisions
imported>Giangiacomo Gerla |
imported>Giangiacomo Gerla |
||
Line 2: | Line 2: | ||
As in classical logic, in fuzzy logic an interpretation of a first order language, is obtained by a domain ''D'' and by associating every constant with an element of ''D'' and every n-ary operation name with an n-ary function in ''D''. Instead, the interpretation of the predicate names is different from classical logic since an ''n''-ary predicate name is interpreted by an n-ary fuzzy relation in ''D'', i.e. a map ''r'' from <math>D^n</math> to [0,1]. This since in fuzzy logic properties which are "vague" are admitted. Such a kind of semantics was proposed long time by people interested in first order multi-valued logic, obviously. As an example, since 1996 in the book "Continuous model theory" by Chang and Kisler all the main semantics notions for fuzzy logic where defined in a theoretical setting. Now, even if from a semantical point of view fuzzy logic is not different from first order multi-valued logic, in the deduction apparatus one manifests a basic difference. In fact, in multi-valued logic the deduction operator is a tool to associate every (classical) set of axioms with the related (classical) set of theorems. Also, several authors limite our attention to the generation of the set of valid formulas. From such a point of view the paradigm of the deduction in multi-valued logic is not different in nature from the one of classical logic. Instead in fuzzy logic the notion of [[approximate reasoning]] is crucial. This notion, which is defined by fixing a fuzzy set of logical axioms and a set of graded inference rules, enables us to associate any fuzzy set of proper axioms with the related fuzzy subset of consequences. | As in classical logic, in fuzzy logic an interpretation of a first order language, is obtained by a domain ''D'' and by associating every constant with an element of ''D'' and every n-ary operation name with an n-ary function in ''D''. Instead, the interpretation of the predicate names is different from classical logic since an ''n''-ary predicate name is interpreted by an n-ary fuzzy relation in ''D'', i.e. a map ''r'' from <math>D^n</math> to [0,1]. This since in fuzzy logic properties which are "vague" are admitted. Such a kind of semantics was proposed long time by people interested in first order multi-valued logic, obviously. As an example, since 1996 in the book "Continuous model theory" by Chang and Kisler all the main semantics notions for fuzzy logic where defined in a theoretical setting. Now, even if from a semantical point of view fuzzy logic is not different from first order multi-valued logic, in the deduction apparatus one manifests a basic difference. In fact, in multi-valued logic the deduction operator is a tool to associate every (classical) set of axioms with the related (classical) set of theorems. Also, several authors limite our attention to the generation of the set of valid formulas. From such a point of view the paradigm of the deduction in multi-valued logic is not different in nature from the one of classical logic. Instead in fuzzy logic the notion of [[approximate reasoning]] is crucial. This notion, which is defined by fixing a fuzzy set of logical axioms and a set of graded inference rules, enables us to associate any fuzzy set of proper axioms with the related fuzzy subset of consequences. | ||
Onother basic difference is in the origin and in the agenda. Indeed the origin of fuzzy logic is in control and its aim is to find applications, in general. Instead, multi-valued logic originates from philosophical and theoretical questions. | Onother basic difference is in the origin and in the agenda. Indeed the origin of fuzzy logic is in control and its aim is to find applications, in general. Instead, multi-valued logic originates from philosophical and theoretical questions. | ||
== The fuzzy models == | |||
Given a first order language, an interpretation is ... | |||
== Approximate reasonings == | |||
== Is fuzzy logic a proper extension of classical logic ? == | |||
The interpretation of the logical connectives in fuzzy logic is ''conservative'' in the sense that its restriction to {0,1} coincides with the classical one. This fact can be interpreted by saying that fuzzy logic is conservative and that it is a proper extension of classical logic. On the other hand it is evident also that fuzzy logic is defined inside classical mathematics and therefore inside classical logic. Then, as a matther of fact fuzzy logic is a (small) chapter of classical mathematics. This means that, differently from intuitionistic logic, fuzzy logic cannot be considered as an alternative philosophy in a trict sense. | |||
=== Effectiveness for fuzzy subsets === | === Effectiveness for fuzzy subsets === |
Revision as of 01:12, 1 July 2007
Formal fuzzy logic: a new chapter of multi-valued logic
As in classical logic, in fuzzy logic an interpretation of a first order language, is obtained by a domain D and by associating every constant with an element of D and every n-ary operation name with an n-ary function in D. Instead, the interpretation of the predicate names is different from classical logic since an n-ary predicate name is interpreted by an n-ary fuzzy relation in D, i.e. a map r from to [0,1]. This since in fuzzy logic properties which are "vague" are admitted. Such a kind of semantics was proposed long time by people interested in first order multi-valued logic, obviously. As an example, since 1996 in the book "Continuous model theory" by Chang and Kisler all the main semantics notions for fuzzy logic where defined in a theoretical setting. Now, even if from a semantical point of view fuzzy logic is not different from first order multi-valued logic, in the deduction apparatus one manifests a basic difference. In fact, in multi-valued logic the deduction operator is a tool to associate every (classical) set of axioms with the related (classical) set of theorems. Also, several authors limite our attention to the generation of the set of valid formulas. From such a point of view the paradigm of the deduction in multi-valued logic is not different in nature from the one of classical logic. Instead in fuzzy logic the notion of approximate reasoning is crucial. This notion, which is defined by fixing a fuzzy set of logical axioms and a set of graded inference rules, enables us to associate any fuzzy set of proper axioms with the related fuzzy subset of consequences. Onother basic difference is in the origin and in the agenda. Indeed the origin of fuzzy logic is in control and its aim is to find applications, in general. Instead, multi-valued logic originates from philosophical and theoretical questions.
The fuzzy models
Given a first order language, an interpretation is ...
Approximate reasonings
Is fuzzy logic a proper extension of classical logic ?
The interpretation of the logical connectives in fuzzy logic is conservative in the sense that its restriction to {0,1} coincides with the classical one. This fact can be interpreted by saying that fuzzy logic is conservative and that it is a proper extension of classical logic. On the other hand it is evident also that fuzzy logic is defined inside classical mathematics and therefore inside classical logic. Then, as a matther of fact fuzzy logic is a (small) chapter of classical mathematics. This means that, differently from intuitionistic logic, fuzzy logic cannot be considered as an alternative philosophy in a trict sense.
Effectiveness for fuzzy subsets
The notions of a "decidable subset" and "recursively enumerable subset" are basic ones for classical mathematics and classical logic. Then, the question of a suitable extension of such concepts to fuzzy set theory arises. A first proposal in such a direction was made by E.S. Santos by the notions of fuzzy Turing machine, Markov normal fuzzy algorithm and fuzzy program. Successively, L. Biacino and G. Gerla proposed the following definition where Ü denotes the set of rational numbers in [0,1].
Definition A fuzzy subset μ : S [0,1] of a set S is recursively enumerable if a recursive map h : S×N Ü exists such that, for every x in S, the function h(x,n) is increasing with respect to n and μ(x) = lim h(x,n). We say that μ is decidable if both μ and its complement –μ are recursively enumerable.
An extension of such a theory to the general case of the L-subsets is proposed in a paper by G. Gerla where one refers to the theory of effective domains. It is an open question to give supports for a Church thesis for fuzzy logic claiming that the proposed notion of recursive enumerability for fuzzy subsets is the adequate one. To this aim, further investigations on the notions of fuzzy grammar and fuzzy Turing machine should be necessary (see for example Wiedermann's paper).
Effectiveness for fuzzy logic
Define the set Val of valid formulas as the set of formulas assuming constantly value equal to 1. Then it is possible to prove that among the usual first order logics only Goedel logic has a recursively enumerable set of valid formulas. In the case of Lukasiewicz and product logic, for example, Val is not recursively enumerable (see B. Scarpellini, Belluce). Such a fact was extensively examined in the book of Hajek. Neverthless, from these results we cannot conclude that these logics are not effective and therefore that an axiomatization is not possible. Indeed, if we refer to the just exposed notion of effectiveness for fuzzy sets, then the following theorem holds true (provided that the deduction apparatus of the fuzzy logic satisfies some obvious effectiveness property).
Theorem. Any axiomatizable fuzzy theory is recursively enumerable. In particular, the fuzzy set of logically true formulas is recursively enumerable in spite of the fact that the crisp set of valid formulas is not recursively enumerable, in general. Moreover, any axiomatizable and complete theory is decidable.
It is an open question to utilize the notion of recursively enumerable fuzzy subset to find an extension of Gödel’s theorems to fuzzy logic.
See also
- Neuro-fuzzy
- Fuzzy subalgebra
- Fuzzy associative matrix
- FuzzyCLIPS expert system
- Fuzzy control system
- Fuzzy set
- Paradox of the heap
- Pattern recognition
- Rough set
Bibliography
- Biacino L., Gerla G., Fuzzy logic, continuity and effectiveness, Archive for Mathematical Logic, 41, (2002), 643-667.
- Chang C. C.,Keisler H. J., Continuous Model Theory, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1996.
- Cignoli R., D’Ottaviano I. M. L. , Mundici D. , ‘’Algebraic Foundations of Many-Valued Reasoning’’. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1999.
- Cox E., The Fuzzy Systems Handbook (1994), ISBN 0-12-194270-8
- Elkan C.. The Paradoxical Success of Fuzzy Logic. November 1993. Available from Elkan's home page.
- Hájek P., Metamathematics of fuzzy logic. Kluwer 1998.
- Hájek P., Fuzzy logic and arithmetical hierarchy, Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 3, (1995), 359-363.
- Klir G. and Folger T., Fuzzy Sets, Uncertainty, and Information (1988), ISBN 0-13-345984-5.
- Klir G. and Bo Yuan, Fuzzy Sets and Fuzzy Logic (1995) ISBN 0-13-101171-5
- Gerla G., Effectiveness and Multivalued Logics, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 71 (2006) 137-162.
- Montagna F., Three complexity problems in quantified fuzzy logic. Studia Logica, 68,(2001), 143-152.
- Novák V., Perfilieva I, Mockor J., Mathematical Principles of Fuzzy Logic, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, (1999).
- Scarpellini B., Die Nichaxiomatisierbarkeit des unendlichwertigen Prädikatenkalküls von Łukasiewicz, J. of Symbolic Logic, 27,(1962), 159-170.
- Zimmermann H., Fuzzy Set Theory and its Applications (2001), ISBN 0-7923-7435-5.
- Kevin M. Passino and Stephen Yurkovich, Fuzzy Control, Addison Wesley Longman, Menlo Park, CA, 1998.
- Wiedermann J. , Characterizing the super-Turing computing power and efficiency of classical fuzzy Turing machines, Theor. Comput. Sci. 317, (2004), 61-69.
- Zadeh L.A., Fuzzy algorithms, Information and Control, 5,(1968), 94-102.
- Zadeh L.A., Fuzzy Sets, ‘’Information and Control’’, 8 (1965) 338353.
- Zemankova-Leech, M., Fuzzy Relational Data Bases (1983), Ph. D. Dissertation, Florida State University.