Politics: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Nick Gardner
(Theories of government (headings only))
imported>Nick Gardner
(→‎Theories of government: decision-making)
Line 18: Line 18:


==Theories of government==
==Theories of government==
===Decision-making===
Government conduct  has been  influenced as much by  decision-making rationales as by  ideologies -  there have been  tyrannical  democracies  as well as a benevolent despotisms. It might appear rational for every  government decision to be based upon an evaluation of its expected consequences - a rationale that is termed [[consequentialism]] -  but that  rationale is far from being the general rule. Governments have, to varying extents, been influenced by [[deontism]], that is to say  by what they perceive to be  principles specifying  actions  that must always to be done or  must always  be avoided.  Some such principles originate from religious codes such as the Ten Commandments or the Moslem Sharia,  and some are socially-determined  concepts of rights, obligations and duties, such as equity,  fair dealing  and family reponsibilities. Consequentialist acceptance of such principles is conditional upon the absence  of  significantly  harmful  consequences, but  deontist acceptance is absolute and without exception.  The governing principle known as [[paternalism]] substitutes that government’s conception of desirable outcomes from that of the governed, either for deontalist reasons, or on the ground that the government has the better understanding of the true interests of the governed. At the other extreme is governing behaviour known as [[populism]], under which decisions are influenced by transitory or ill-informed surges of public opinion. ''[[Utilitarianism]]'' <ref>[http://www.utilitarianism.com/mill1.htm, John Stuart Mill ''Utilitarianism'']</ref>  as put forward by [[John Stuart Mill]],  treats all of those influence as aberrations and advocates decision-making that is directed solely at the improvement of the welfare of those affected ''as they themselves see it''. Under that theory, individuals  are deemed to delegate to government the responsibility for determining the physical consequences of their actions, but  are deemed to  be  the sole judge of the resulting social consequences.  That theory is in turn rejected in [[John Rawls]]’ [[A Theory of Justice]] <ref> John Rawls ''A Theory of Justice ''  Harvard University Press 1971</ref>  under which decisions must conform to  the "[[difference principle]]" which permits  only those  inequalities of welfare  that benefit the least well-off in the community. Dissenting also from that theory,  the philosopher [[Robert Nozick]] has argued <ref> Robert Nozick  ''Anarchy, State and Utopia''  Basic Books 1974 </ref> that each individual has an inalienable right to his own abilities and creations, making it ethically unacceptable for a government to seek to re-allocate the resulting  benefits. This account of  the influences upon government conduct has been based upon the assumption that  governments govern on behalf of the governed, but the theory of [[Public Choice]] <ref> James Buchanan and Gordon Tullock ''The Calculus of Consent''.  University of Michigan Press 1962</ref> leads to a different conclusion.  That theory assumes that the actions of politicians and civil servants are directed by economic motives, and that they are thus influenced more by self-interest than by a wish to serve the public.


===Legitimacy===
===Legitimacy===
===Decision-making===


==Current forms of government==
==Current forms of government==

Revision as of 08:47, 20 November 2007

This article is developed but not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
Timelines [?]
Addendum [?]
Index [?]
Glossary [?]
 
This editable, developed Main Article is subject to a disclaimer.

Politics is about living together in communities. As "social animals" , humans have always tended to form groups, the better to enjoy the benefits of cooperation and mutual defence; and groups have merged to form tribes, city-states and nation-states. The subject-matter of politics is the conduct of relations within and between those groups. It includes beliefs concerning the proper regulation of that conduct, and the systems and institutions that have been adopted for doing so.

Ideologies

The functions of ideology

A widely accepted set of beliefs about social behaviour may be termed an ideology if its rationale is known, or a myth if it is not. The term ideology is often associated in people’s minds with dogmatism and intolerance, but in fact, every society has needed a set of shared assumptions to provide it with a settled view about living together. That settled view has typically included conscious beliefs that are topics of everyday discussion, and subconscious attitudes that are seldom examined. It has enabled generally acceptable outcomes to be achieved without debating their underlying rationale. But what group members have considered to be a prized tradition, may have appeared to outsiders to be an irrational ideology.

Social ideologies

Myths and ideologies about personal status and the nature of authority are part of the foundation of every political ideology. For example, the medieval myth of "the Chain of Being" [1] which defined the hierarchical status of every living thing, was the foundation of feudalism, and its subconscious influence is believed to underlie more recent attitudes to race and gender. And in the nineteenth century, the myth of "the ladder of life" [2] which envisaged evolution as generating a process in which each emerging type of human being is an improvement on its predecessor, was the rationale for a political ideology of the survival of the fittest known as "Social Darwinism" [3]. The formation of groups has led to “we/they” myths about the superiority of members over non-members [4] and the creation of ethnic and nationalist ideologies.

Political ideologies

Several political ideologies have made repeated appearances over the course of history. Authoritarianism, in the form of government by a trained elite, was advocated in the 4th century BCE by Plato [5], it was advocated in the 17th century by Thomas Hobbes [6] as the need for a controlling authority to prevent the chaos of a “war of all against all”, and it emerged again in the 20th century as the philosophy of Nazism [7] . Democracy, in the form that gave every citizen a right to participate in every communal decision, made a brief appearance in Pericles’ Athens in the 6th century BCE [8] , but was rejected in that form for centuries thereafter. In particular, the founders of the United States constitution rejected it in favour of "representation ingrafted upon democracy" as advocated in Thomas Paine’s Rights of Man [9]. The concept of Representative Government, in which the people delegate decision-making powers to an authority on condition that it acts in their interest, had been put forward in the 17th century in the second of John Locke’s treatises On Civil Government [10] and was further developed in the 19th century in John Stuart Mill’s Representative Government [11]. The ideology of Socialism, as the belief that all property should be communally owned, was put forward in the 16th century in Thomas More’s ''Utopia'' [12] ; publicised in the early 19th century by Henri de Saint-Simon [13] and developed into an influential creed in Karl Marx’s Das Kapital. [14]. The ideologies of Liberalism and Libertarianism are attributable to several of the philosophers of the enlightenment. Both of those ideologies are concerned to preserve individual freedom from state interference, but Liberals, such as Friedrich von Hayek [15] , acknowledge the need to impose charges for good that must be financed by the stare, whereas Libertarians do not. In opposition to those beliefs, the ideology of Communitarianism that was put forward by Amitai Etzioni [16], lays greater emphasis upon the contribution of community activity to individual welfare.

Theories of government

Decision-making

Government conduct has been influenced as much by decision-making rationales as by ideologies - there have been tyrannical democracies as well as a benevolent despotisms. It might appear rational for every government decision to be based upon an evaluation of its expected consequences - a rationale that is termed consequentialism - but that rationale is far from being the general rule. Governments have, to varying extents, been influenced by deontism, that is to say by what they perceive to be principles specifying actions that must always to be done or must always be avoided. Some such principles originate from religious codes such as the Ten Commandments or the Moslem Sharia, and some are socially-determined concepts of rights, obligations and duties, such as equity, fair dealing and family reponsibilities. Consequentialist acceptance of such principles is conditional upon the absence of significantly harmful consequences, but deontist acceptance is absolute and without exception. The governing principle known as paternalism substitutes that government’s conception of desirable outcomes from that of the governed, either for deontalist reasons, or on the ground that the government has the better understanding of the true interests of the governed. At the other extreme is governing behaviour known as populism, under which decisions are influenced by transitory or ill-informed surges of public opinion. Utilitarianism [17] as put forward by John Stuart Mill, treats all of those influence as aberrations and advocates decision-making that is directed solely at the improvement of the welfare of those affected as they themselves see it. Under that theory, individuals are deemed to delegate to government the responsibility for determining the physical consequences of their actions, but are deemed to be the sole judge of the resulting social consequences. That theory is in turn rejected in John RawlsA Theory of Justice [18] under which decisions must conform to the "difference principle" which permits only those inequalities of welfare that benefit the least well-off in the community. Dissenting also from that theory, the philosopher Robert Nozick has argued [19] that each individual has an inalienable right to his own abilities and creations, making it ethically unacceptable for a government to seek to re-allocate the resulting benefits. This account of the influences upon government conduct has been based upon the assumption that governments govern on behalf of the governed, but the theory of Public Choice [20] leads to a different conclusion. That theory assumes that the actions of politicians and civil servants are directed by economic motives, and that they are thus influenced more by self-interest than by a wish to serve the public.


Legitimacy

Current forms of government

Political Institutions

References